A Single Comment — Permalink
© ICCforum.com, 2010–2024. All rights reserved. Policies | Guidelines
Featured Comments
- SusanKnisely: I work with a good number complex crime victims. The population is those who are victims of terrorism and human trafficking; women, children and their families. My commentary is based on experience with these victims rather than theory. Sadly, in America, our legal system fails especially in complex cases. One reason I discovered is that many attorneys don't want to take on a complex case as they could earn the same income from a "easy," case. Second is a resistance by the private legal system... (more)
- Cowdery: It is to be hoped that the ICC, like other courts, would be able to play a crime prevention role in respect of the offences with which it deals; but a few basic points need to be made in the interests of realism. First it is not like other courts. Domestic criminal courts have jurisdiction over a geographical area covered by law enforcement officials who feed offences into those courts. There is reach, permanence and consistency of action. There is a real risk of detection and... (more)
- Kimia: Coercive Diplomacy: An ICC Approach to Minimize Human Rights Atrocities Argument Instead of focusing on a retribution approach, the ICC should think about using a coercive diplomacy framework in some cases. At a time when perpetrators have committed crimes and are able to wage ongoing human rights abuses, this approach may induce short-term deterrence. Introduction... (more)
- elio: Argument To achieve long-term deterrence and prevention of crimes, the ICC must first be seen as a legitimate and credible threat. To be seen as a credible threat, the ICC should employ two methods. First, the ICC should take a broad view of the “complementarity” principle. Second, when the ICC decides to issue an arrest warrant, it should resolutely... (more)
- Patrick S Wegner: Interesting post Jonathan. I think the idea of proactive complementarity goes into the right direction, but there are also some dangers in trying to rush domestic prosecutions. The International Crimes Division (ICD) of the Ugandan High Court would be a good example for the type of domestic prosecutions furthered by the ICC that you suggest. The Court was set up in the scope of the accountability discussions during the Juba negotiations with the Lord's Resistance Army. The need to talk about... (more)
- grant2012: ICC Should Plea-Bargain to Prevent Crime and Bring Restorative Justice to Victims Argument The International Criminal Court (ICC) should utilize plea bargaining with criminal leaders prior to trial to remove criminal leaders who enflame hostilities from their positions of power. By removing criminal leaders, the ICC can serve its mission by preventing future crimes emanating from that conflict and... (more)
- Sean.Lowe: Economic Sanctions & Capacity Building: Two Approaches to Prevent Atrocities Most Effectively Argument Because the ICC does not address crime with all of the traditional tools of punishment, it follows that the ICC must look to creative, non-traditional approaches for it to maximize its crime prevention impact. The ICC, then, should focus on two specific priorities, the first of... (more)
- nmoley: Argument The ICC’s overall effectiveness would be improved if it undertook a clear rule delineating when a state is “unwilling or unable” to prosecute on its own. In order to achieve the aims of preventing crime, promoting justice, and ending impunity for perpetrators of serious crimes, the ICC must continually legitimize itself in the eyes of the international community. At the same time, the... (more)
- jonathan.tobin: Argument The International Criminal Court can increase its legitimacy by focusing upon a strategy of complementarity. Such a strategy would mean that the ICC works closely with member states to develop and act upon agreed-upon standards of prosecution in cases of war crimes and other results of widespread violence. This strategy would also increase the visibility of the ICC such that it would not be seen as a... (more)
- davidlee211: Positive Complementarity: Prospects and Limits Argument In order to maximize its effectiveness in the prevention of crimes, the ICC should continue to encourage and assist States Parties in undertaking national prosecutions of international crimes through what is called “positive complementarity.” While there are significant obstacles to positive complementarity, there are several ways to overcome them and to... (more)
- G. L.: Argument The International Criminal Court (ICC), as an isolated legal institution, has minimal deterrent effect on the crimes it has jurisdiction over. However, it is a part of a greater trend in international law fostering universal condemnation for these crimes and thus creating an environment where such crimes are unsupportable and indefensible. I. Introduction The preamble of the... (more)
- Scott McDonald: Argument In order for OTP to maximize its prevention of crime, it must base its policies on a cost-benefit model of deterrence. This model advances the idea that an actor will stop (or not begin) rights violating behavior when the cost of that behavior outweighs its benefits. There are different classes of actors that the ICC must work towards deterring however, and each class has different considerations that play... (more)
- danterzian: Professor Goldstone praises the ICC as the world's best hope for preventing crimes against humanity. But it's just that: A hope. He argues that the key to achieving justice and preventing crimes is universal ratification of the Rome Statute. I disagree. Signatories aren't the key; soldiers are. The Democratic Republic of Congo, for example, signed the Rome Statute. And the ICC indicted Congolese General Bosco Ntaganda. Yet he lives openly, luxuriously and lawlessly. (http://motherjones.com/... (more)
- Scott McDonald: I agree with Mr. Goldstone that the emerging doctrine of Responsibility to Protect (R2P) represents a key opportunity for the ICC to maximize its crime prevention capabilities. However, its usefulness seems limited by the recently defined crime of aggression, which allows for force only in the traditional cases of self-defense or U.N.S.C. authorization. While the U.N.S.C. is to be applauded for utilizing an R2P rationale for the first time following the limited adoption of the doctrine at the... (more)
- Alma Pekmezovic: Introduction The ICC has been established with jurisdiction over various types of crimes, including: genocide, war crimes and crimes against humanity. These crimes affect “international peace and security.”1 The main purpose of the Court is to end impunity for these crimes and bring individuals who have committed such crimes to justice.2 At the most basic level, the function of the ICC is to... (more)
- Cecilia: Argument The International Criminal Court should actively employ positive complementarity and defer to non-prosecutorial methods when appropriate in preventing crime. Deterring crime involves more than prosecution by the ICC. Changing societal norms and standards through positive complementarity and alternative justice mechanisms may have a long-term preventative impact. Introduction If the ICC... (more)
- danterzian: Argument The ICC’s threat of punishment, while disincentivizing prospective criminals from committing crimes, ineffectively disincentives current criminals from committing further crimes. Thus, if the ICC wishes to prevent crimes in ongoing conflicts, it should employ practices beyond threatening punishment such as pre-arrest plea bargaining. Introduction Threatening punishment deters... (more)
Comment on the Prevention Question: “What measures should be taken to maximize the crime prevention impact of the International Criminal Court?”
Argument
The International Criminal Court should actively employ positive complementarity and defer to non-prosecutorial methods when appropriate in preventing crime. Deterring crime involves more than prosecution by the ICC. Changing societal norms and standards through positive complementarity and alternative justice mechanisms may have a long-term preventative impact.
Introduction
If the ICC is to succeed in maximizing crime prevention, the ICC must strategically employ justice mechanisms and defer to alternative non-prosecutorial methods when appropriate. Preventing atrocities requires the ICC to defer to alternative non-prosecutorial methods, including truth commissions and amnesty. When the cost of prosecution means continued tyranny or bloodshed, the ICC should carefully weigh the benefits and costs of prosecution. However, the ICC should not defer to non-prosecutorial methods that undercut its raison d’être unless the alternative methods can accomplish similar objectives.1
Accordingly, I argue that maximizing crime prevention by the ICC necessitates a look at justice and peace mechanisms. In particular, the situation in Uganda illustrates the need for exploring alternative non-prosecutorial methods in so far as they achieve the primary objectives of the ICC in deterring criminal behavior.
Part I of this comment will discuss the dichotomy between peace and justice in furthering the overarching objects and purposes of the international criminal justice system. In Part II of the comment, I discuss how the ICC can effectively prevent future atrocities through positive complementarity by promulgating justice in the domestic sphere. Part III will discuss the issue of whether the ICC should defer to non-prosecutorial alternatives, and if so, under what circumstances. Finally, Part IV will conclude.
I. Peace or Justice
The Rome Statute’s Preamble envisaged the ICC as a mechanism to contribute to the prevention of “grave crimes [that] threaten the peace, security and well-being of the world.”2 In an armed conflict, where the threat of continued bloodshed is imminent, the decision to prosecute or defer to peace negotiations is a difficult dilemma faced by the ICC Prosecutor. On the one hand, to allow crimes against humanity and genocide, often committed by means of mass murders, dismemberments, kidnappings, and gang rapes, to go unpunished seems to betray the victims of such acts and encourage similar crimes against others.3 On the other hand, when prosecution would derail peace negotiations and fuel a cycle of violence, one must ask whether there is an affirmative duty to prosecute. These are serious considerations that the ICC Prosecutor must grapple with, including the consequences of his decisions.
A. Consequentialist Argument
From a consequentialist perspective, the ICC should select the course of action that will produce the best outcome.4 Under this theory, the ICC should carefully assess various courses of action, given limited information, and choose the action that will produce the most beneficial result. This would largely entail pursuing the course of action that produces a net social benefit in excess of opportunity costs.5 If the total consequences of prosecuting an individual would ultimately be dire rather than beneficial, prosecution should not be pursued.6 Accordingly, the ICC should base its decision to prosecute on the effects of prosecution, including whether it would result in further violence and atrocities or contribute to peace. Thus, one important consideration the ICC must weigh in making a calculated decision to prosecute is whether the course of action would result in less or more violence.
The costs of prosecution not only encompass administrative and judicial costs, but it also includes delaying peace efforts and contributing to long-term instability and violence.7 Under the consequentialist theory, the ICC should defer to alternative justice mechanisms in lieu of prosecution where there is a serious threat of increased violence and the costs of prosecution outweigh the benefits.
A critical restraint on effectively deciding whether to prosecute is the difficulty in accurately predicting the costs and benefits of such a decision. Consideration must be given to both short-term and long-term consequences. Prosecuting a war criminal may produce immediate dire consequences though this may be outweighed by its long-term benefits, such as securing peace. In other circumstances, prosecution may result in serious adverse consequences that may potentially lead to long-term instability and increased violence. Thus, it may be difficult to predict whether an ICC prosecution would deter a future would-be tyrant or incite him or other criminals to commit further atrocities. The paucity of information is one serious obstacle that the ICC Prosecutor must consider in evaluating the ultimate consequences of prosecution.8 Nevertheless, the ICC Prosecutor should defer to non-prosecutorial methods where the negative consequences of prosecution outweigh its benefits.
B. Appropriateness Argument
A countervailing theory to the consequentialist theory is the logic of appropriateness. Decision-makers are driven by rules of appropriate or exemplary behavior and they seek to fulfill the obligations of their role and the ethos, practices and expectations of their institutions.9 Under this theory, actors follow norms because they think it is the right or legitimate thing to do.10 Accordingly, there is an affirmative duty to prosecute because it is morally right. Whether the effects of prosecution negatively outweigh its benefits is immaterial in deciding the proper course of action.
Under this paradigm, achieving justice is essential in the international human rights context. The logic of appropriateness would require the Prosecutor of the ICC to adhere to prosecuting criminals regardless of the outcome or any policy consideration. Whether the outcome contributes to an increase in violence, which results in mass atrocities and bloodshed is inconsequential. The ICC Prosecutor should prosecute those individuals who have allegedly committed human rights violations because it is the legitimate thing to do. Thus, this theory rejects non-prosecutorial methods since it would usurp the functions of the ICC Prosecutor to achieve justice.
In order to maximize crime prevention, the ICC must strategically employ those methods that will contribute to this objective. Because the logic of appropriateness must be rigidly applied and no consideration is given to the effects of prosecution, the logic of appropriateness must be discarded and replaced with the consequentialist theory in deciding whether to prosecute.
II. Positive Complementarity
Positive Complementarity is the idea that the Office of the Prosecutor (OTP) and Chief Prosecutor should encourage states to prosecute domestically.11 The objective of positive complementarity is to strengthen domestic capacity, which arguably will have a long-term preventative impact.12 The ICC can effectively prevent atrocities by encouraging states to establish systems and institutions to try international crimes.
A. Prevention and Complementarity in the International Criminal Court
A criticism of the ICC is that it presumes that the perpetrators of armed conflict are rational decision-makers, and thus are deterred by the threat of prosecution.13 Because mass atrocities occur during a collapse in the public order, assuming perpetrator rationality may be unreasonable.14 Positive complementarity, on the other hand, seems to be a more effective strategy to adopt because of its long-term impact on national judicial systems. The ICC can foster respect for the rule of law both domestically and internationally by adopting positive complementarity and cooperating with states parties to facilitate “ICC-supported transnational networks dedicated to international criminal laws.”15 Over time, strong judicial institutions can stabilize societies by establishing norms that prevent impunity and uphold the idea that no one is above the law. This in turn can strengthen the principles of democracy and the rule of law in a society. Additionally, the ICC can turn to the international community—the UN and other State Parties—to increase diplomatic pressure or encourage individuals to denounce the violations that they might otherwise have ignored.16
B. Positive Complementarity Applied to Uganda
On December 16, 2003, President Museveni referred the matter of the Lord’s Resistance Army (LRA) to the ICC for investigation and prosecution for serious violations of international law.17 In January 2004, Chief Prosecutor Moreno-Ocampo opened an investigation in the region, and after a year-long investigation, the court issued warrants for Joseph Kony, Vincent Otti, Okot Odhiambo, Dominic Ongwen and Raska Lukwiya.18 Although the Ugandan government referred the matter to the ICC, they also promised amnesty for the leaders of the LRA on the condition they disarm and return home.19 The Ugandan government recommended a traditional reconciliation ceremony called “mato oput” in lieu of criminal prosecution.20
The indictments issued by the ICC against the LRA’s leadership have served to bring the LRA to the negotiating table and contributed to the progress of the peace negotiations.21 Since the matter was referred to the ICC, the violence has decreased in Northern Uganda though a peace agreement remains to be signed.22 The Government of Uganda has begun to implement a method to try the perpetrators for international crimes domestically as a result of the ICC’s involvement and demands by the LRA leadership that they not be prosecuted abroad.23 This process has thus far engaged a significant number of leaders in government and civil society whose involvement and outreach efforts can foster respect for the institution and trials that result.24 The “envisioned war crime division of the Ugandan High Court” will reflect Ugandan and international standards of justice and incorporate traditional justice mechanisms.25 Although the impact of this collaborative process between local leaders and international advisors remains to be seen, the OTP’s active engagement of States Parties seems to contribute to the progression of the Ugandan peace process “in both expanding the judicial system and engaging various parts of society in the process.”26 The ICC’s involvement in Uganda will be critical in fostering norms and standards that uphold the rule of law. Moreover, the establishment of a war crimes division will be one step in the right direction for establishing a stable judicial system and eventually a stable government.
III. Non-prosecutorial Methods
Victim communities seek justice in Uganda through traditional reintegration ceremonies whereas the ICC Prosecutor seeks justice through criminal prosecutions.27 Because the Rome Statute is silent on amnesty and truth commissions, the statute might allow sub rosa recognition of amnesty or other alternative justice mechanisms (AJM) in certain circumstances.28 Those circumstances consist of the following: (1) Article 16 deferral resolution, where the Security Council would require the ICC to suspend the Ugandan prosecution as a threat to international peace29; (2) Article 20 ne bis in idem, Ugandan AJM can be treated as prior prosecution blocking subsequent ICC proceedings30; (3) Article 53 prosecutorial discretion, which allows the Prosecutor to decline to prosecute in the interest of justice31; and (4) Article 17 inadmissibility,32 where Ugandan AJM would render the case inadmissible under the principle of complementarity.33
A. Alternative Justice Mechanisms
Through AJM the ICC can foster the rule of law in regions that have been torn by conflict and violence. This can in turn have a tremendous deterrent effect. One-size fits all justice does not seem to work where the threat of prosecution remains illusory. AJM may be a more effective measure in deterring criminal behavior because it would utilize traditional methods of justice, specific to a certain region or culture to accomplish the same objectives of the ICC—advancing justice and punishing criminals. Before deferring to AJM, the ICC must ensure that the AJM in question will accomplish the objective of crime prevention. The AJM must be assessed based on a two-part inquiry: (1) whether the AJM is per se legitimate, and (2) whether the AJM would be necessary to secure peace.
1. Uganda’s AJM
The threshold requirement of legitimacy focuses on whether the agreement is legitimate. Legitimacy requires the agreement to be promulgated by a democratically elected government or international body, rather than a government motivated by covering up its own international crimes.34 The AJM must represent the people and adhere to a principle of nondiscrimination. Additionally, the AJM should hold those culpable of perpetrating crimes responsible regardless of their status or affiliation to the government or a criminal organization.
The decision for Ugandan AJM appears to be legitimate because it was first proposed by Acholi leaders, rather than the government.35 Unlike the truth commission established in Uganda during the 1970s, it does not seem that the Ugandan government will adopt the AJM to protect itself.36 Ugandan AJM would represent the interest of the people, including the most marginalized segments of society which initially called for AJM.37 Additionally, Ugandan AJM seems to be widely supported by the Acholi and victims who desire truth commissions and mato oput.38 At the outset, Ugandan AJM seems to be a legitimate alternative to prosecution under the ICC.
Secondly, the Ugandan AJM is necessary to secure peace within the region. The replacement of ICC prosecution with AJM in the Uganda situation may be critical in furthering peace negotiations between the LRA and the government.39 The LRA maintains that before they can sign any peace deal the warrants against Kony and his top commanders must be dropped.40 Thus, Uganda’s request for the ICC to withdraw its warrants seems necessary to securing peace.
In attempting to secure peace, Uganda may implement various mechanisms. For example, a truth commission process such as that used in South Africa can serve to reveal the perpetrators of crimes and foster condemnation of those crimes and censure the perpetrators. South Africa’s Truth and Reconciliation Commission (TRC) model illustrates how public condemnation and reparations for victims can serve a deterrent effect.41 Accordingly, Uganda should consider a truth commission to morally condemn the crimes and the perpetrators through public disgrace, stigma, and censure, as well as incorporate reparations for the victims.42
Furthermore, Ugandan AJM may come in the form of mato oput, a traditional justice mechanism that combines shaming with a compensatory remedy. The “mato oput” ceremony requires that the perpetrator of the crime admit wrongdoing to the victim, ask forgiveness, and pay compensation.43 Given its communal origins, shaming is traditionally part of the Acholi culture, and is incorporated into mato oput.44 “The local shaming punishment might be as close to proportional punishment as an ICC sentence.”45 Mato oput is not without flaws as it would require perpetrators of crime, many being children soldiers, to pay compensation to the victims. Presumably, these children soldiers would not have any financial resources for victim reparations.
Despite these challenges, mato oput and the truth commission seem to be the best alternative for securing peace in Uganda while also advancing the principle of justice. For such mechanisms to have a deterrent effect, the truth commission report and the outcome of mato oput must be widely publicized. Similar to prosecution, it may be difficult to measure the actual deterrent effect of Ugandan AJM. Nevertheless, AJM achieves two important objectives: securing peace and advancing justice.
IV. Conclusion
In conclusion, the ICC should employ positive complementarity or defer to alternative justice mechanisms in order to maximize crime prevention. Under positive complementarity, the ICC can effectively prevent atrocities by encouraging states to establish systems and institutions to try international crimes. This in turn can foster a respect for the rule of law that will likely have positive long-term reinforcing effects. Furthermore, when prosecution would result in increased violence and bloodshed, the ICC should defer to alternative justice mechanisms. Consequently, both peace and justice can be achieved under these two methods.
Endnotes — (click the footnote reference number, or ↩ symbol, to return to location in text).
Linda M. Keller, Achieving Peace with Justice: The International Criminal Court and Ugandan Alternative Justice Mechanisms, 23 Conn. J. Int’l L. 209, 419 (2008). ↩
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, Preamble, Adopted by the United Nations Diplomatic Conference of Plenipotentiaries on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court, July 17 1998, UN Doc. A/CONF.183/9 [hereinafter cited as Rome Statute]. ↩
Eric Blumenson, The Challenge of a Global Standard of Justice: Peace, Pluralism, and Punishment at the International Criminal Court, 44 Colum. J. Transnat’l L. 801, 819 (2006). ↩
Id. at 823. ↩
Id. ↩
Id. at 824. ↩
See Eric S. Fish, Peace Through Complementarity: Solving the Ex Post Problem in the International Criminal Court Prosecutions, 119 Yale L.J.1703, 1708 (2010). ↩
Blumenson, supra note 3, at 828. ↩
See James G. March and Johan P. Olsen, The Logic of Appropriateness 3-14 (Center for European Studies University of Oslo Arena Working Paper 2004), available online. ↩
See James Fearon and Alexander Wendt, Handbook of International Relations, 60-63 (Sage Publications, 2002). ↩
Katherine A. Marshall, Prevention and Complementarity in the International Criminal Court: A Positive Approach, 17 Hum. Rts. Br. 21, 22 (Winter 2010), available online.. ↩
Id. ↩
Id. at 24. ↩
Tom Farer, Restraining the Barbarians: Can International Criminal Law Help?, 22 Hum. Rts. Q. 90, 98 (2000). ↩
Marshall, supra note 11, at 25. ↩
Id. ↩
Kimberly Hanlon, Peace or Justice: Now that Peace is being Negotiated in Uganda, Will the ICC Still Pursue Justice?, 14 Tulsa J. Comp. & Int’l L. 295, 304 (2007). ↩
Id. at 304-305. ↩
Hanlon, supra note 17, at 295; see also Manisuli Ssenyonjo, Accountability of Non-State Actors in Uganda For War Crimes and Human Rights Violations: Between Amnesty and the International Criminal Court, 10 J. Conflict & Security L. 405, 419 (2005). ↩
Tristan McConnell, Uganda Sees Local Justice as Key to Peace, Christian Science Monitor, Sept. 8, 2006, available online (during the “mato oput” ceremony, “the perpetrator of a crime meets the victim, admits wrongdoing, asks for forgiveness, and pays compensation. The ritual ends with perpetrator and victim sharing a cup of sheep’s blood mixed with a bitter root.”) ↩
See, e.g. International Crisis Group, Africa Report No. 124: Northern Uganda: Seizing the Opportunity for Peace (April 26, 2007), available online. ↩
Uganda Violence: One of the World’s Most Neglected Crises, Reuters Alertnet, Sept. 17, 2009, available online (last visited May 11, 2011). ↩
Michael A. Newton, The Complementarity Conundrum: Are We Watching Evolution or Evisceration?, 8 Santa Clara J. Int’l L. 115 (2009). ↩
Marshall, supra note 11, at 26. ↩
Id. ↩
Id. ↩
Jeffrey Gettleman, Uganda Peace Hinges on Amnesty for Brutality, N.Y. Times, Sept. 15, 2006, available online (last visited May 11, 2011). ↩
Keller, supra note 1, at 238. ↩
See Rome Statute, supra note 3, art. 16 (Deferral of investigation or prosecution: “No investigation or prosecution may be commenced or proceeded with under this Statute for a period of 12 months after the Security Council, in a resolution adopted under Chapter VII of the Charter of the United Nations, has requested the Court to that effect: that request may be renewed by the Council under the same conditions.”). ↩
See Rome Statute, supra note 3, art. 20(Ne bis in idem: “3. No person who has been tried by another court for conduct also proscribed under article 6, 7, 8, or 8 bis shall be tried by the Court with respect to the same conduct unless the proceedings in the other court: (a) Were for the purpose of shielding the person concerned from criminal responsibility for crimes within the jurisdiction of the Court; or (b) Otherwise were not conducted independently or impartially in accordance with the norms of due process recognized by international law and were conducted in a manner which, in the circumstances, was inconsistent with an intent to bring the person concerned to justice.”). ↩
See Rome Statute, supra note 3, art. 53 (“Initiation of an investigation […] 2. If, upon investigation, the Prosecutor concludes that there is not a sufficient basis for a prosecution because: […] (c) A prosecution is not in the interests of justice, taking into account all the circumstances, including the gravity of the crime, the interests of victims, and the age or infirmity of the alleged perpetrator, and his or her role in the alleged crime.”). ↩
See Rome Statute, supra note 3, art. 17 (“Issues of admissibility 1. Having regard to paragraph 10 of the Preamble and article 1, the Court shall determine that a case is inadmissible where: (a) The case is being investigated or prosecuted by a State which has jurisdiction over it, unless the State is unwilling or unable genuinely to carry out the investigation or prosecution.”); see also William W. Burke-White, Shaping the Contours of Domestic Justice: The International Criminal Court and an Admissibility Challenge in the Uganda Situation, 7 J. Int’l Crim. Just. 257, 268-275 (2009). ↩
Keller, supra note 1, at 238. ↩
Mahnoush H. Arsanjani and W. Michael Reisman, The Law-in-Action of the International Criminal Court, 99 Am. J. Int’l L. 385, 393 (2005). ↩
Keller, supra note 1, at 238. ↩
Id. ↩
Adam Branch, International Justice, Local Injustice: The International Criminal Court in Northern Uganda Disssent, Summer 2004, at 22, 24. ↩
Kasaija Phillip Apuuli, The ICC Arrest Warrants for the Lord’s Resistance Army Leaders and Peace Prospects for Northern Uganda, 4. J. Int’l Crim. Just. 179, 183-185 (2006). ↩
Julian Ku and Jide Nzelibe, Do International Criminal Tribunals Deter or Exacerbate Humanitarian Atrocities?, 84 Wash. U. L. Rev. 777, 820 (2006); see also Reuters, Uganda Aide Criticizes Court over Warrants, N.Y. Times, Oct. 9. 2005, available online, (last visited May 11, 2011). ↩
Uganda rebels in fresh truce, BBC, Jan. 12, 2009, available online, (last visited May 11, 2011). ↩
Blumenson, supra note 4, at 865. ↩
Alexander K.A. Greenawalt, Justice Without Politics? Prosecutorial Discretion And the International Criminal Court, 39 N.Y.U. J. Int’l L. & Pol. 583, 614 (2007). ↩
Hanlon, supra note 17, at 306. ↩
Keller, supra note 1, at 269. ↩
Id. ↩